home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Subject: Sci.physics Frequently Asked Questions - May 1994 - Part 4/4
- Newsgroups: sci.physics,sci.physics.particle,alt.sci.physics.new-theories,news.answers,sci.answers,alt.answers
- From: sichase@csa2.lbl.gov (SCOTT I CHASE)
- Date: 30 Apr 1994 17:02 PST
-
- Archive-name: physics-faq/part4
- Last-modified: 26-APR-1994
-
- --------------------------------------------------------------------------------
- FREQUENTLY ASKED QUESTIONS ON SCI.PHYSICS - Part 4/4
- --------------------------------------------------------------------------------
- Item 22.
-
- Why do Mirrors Reverse Left and Right? updated 04-MAR-1994 by SIC
- -------------------------------------- original by Scott I. Chase
-
- The simple answer is that they don't. Look in a mirror and wave
- your right hand. On which side of the mirror is the hand that waved? The
- right side, of course.
-
- Mirrors DO reverse In/Out. Imaging holding an arrow in your hand.
- If you point it up, it will point up in the mirror. If you point it to the
- left, it will point to the left in the mirror. But if you point it toward
- the mirror, it will point right back at you. In and Out are reversed.
-
- If you take a three-dimensional, rectangular, coordinate system,
- (X,Y,Z), and point the Z axis such that the vector equation X x Y = Z is
- satisfied, then the coordinate system is said to be right-handed. Imagine
- Z pointing toward the mirror. X and Y are unchanged (remember the arrows?)
- but Z will point back at you. In the mirror, X x Y = - Z. The image
- contains a left-handed coordinate system.
-
- This has an important effect, familiar mostly to chemists and
- physicists. It changes the chirality, or handedness of objects viewed in
- the mirror. Your left hand looks like a right hand, while your right hand
- looks like a left hand. Molecules often come in pairs called
- stereoisomers, which differ not in the sequence or number of atoms, but
- only in that one is the mirror image of the other, so that no rotation or
- stretching can turn one into the other. Your hands make a good laboratory
- for this effect. They are distinct, even though they both have the same
- components connected in the same way. They are a stereo pair, identical
- except for "handedness".
-
- People sometimes think that mirrors *do* reverse left/right, and
- that the effect is due to the fact that our eyes are aligned horizontally
- on our faces. This can be easily shown to be untrue by looking in any
- mirror with one eye closed!
-
- Reference: _The Left Hand of the Electron_, by Isaac Asimov, contains
- a very readable discussion of handedness and mirrors in physics.
-
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 23.
-
- What is the Mass of a Photon? updated 24-JUL-1992 by SIC
- original by Matt Austern
-
- Or, "Does the mass of an object depend on its velocity?"
-
- This question usually comes up in the context of wondering whether
- photons are really "massless," since, after all, they have nonzero energy.
- The problem is simply that people are using two different definitions of
- mass. The overwhelming consensus among physicists today is to say that
- photons are massless. However, it is possible to assign a "relativistic
- mass" to a photon which depends upon its wavelength. This is based upon
- an old usage of the word "mass" which, though not strictly wrong, is not
- used much today.
-
- The old definition of mass, called "relativistic mass," assigns
- a mass to a particle proportional to its total energy E, and involved
- the speed of light, c, in the proportionality constant:
-
- m = E / c^2. (1)
-
- This definition gives every object a velocity-dependent mass.
-
- The modern definition assigns every object just one mass, an
- invariant quantity that does not depend on velocity. This is given by
-
- m = E_0 / c^2, (2)
-
- where E_0 is the total energy of that object at rest.
-
- The first definition is often used in popularizations, and in some
- elementary textbooks. It was once used by practicing physicists, but for
- the last few decades, the vast majority of physicists have instead used the
- second definition. Sometimes people will use the phrase "rest mass," or
- "invariant mass," but this is just for emphasis: mass is mass. The
- "relativistic mass" is never used at all. (If you see "relativistic mass"
- in your first-year physics textbook, complain! There is no reason for books
- to teach obsolete terminology.)
-
- Note, by the way, that using the standard definition of mass, the
- one given by Eq. (2), the equation "E = m c^2" is *not* correct. Using the
- standard definition, the relation between the mass and energy of an object
- can be written as
-
- E = m c^2 / sqrt(1 -v^2/c^2), (3)
- or as
-
- E^2 = m^2 c^4 + p^2 c^2, (4)
-
- where v is the object's velocity, and p is its momentum.
-
- In one sense, any definition is just a matter of convention. In
- practice, though, physicists now use this definition because it is much
- more convenient. The "relativistic mass" of an object is really just the
- same as its energy, and there isn't any reason to have another word for
- energy: "energy" is a perfectly good word. The mass of an object, though,
- is a fundamental and invariant property, and one for which we do need a
- word.
-
- The "relativistic mass" is also sometimes confusing because it
- mistakenly leads people to think that they can just use it in the Newtonian
- relations
- F = m a (5)
- and
- F = G m1 m2 / r^2. (6)
-
- In fact, though, there is no definition of mass for which these
- equations are true relativistically: they must be generalized. The
- generalizations are more straightforward using the standard definition
- of mass than using "relativistic mass."
-
- Oh, and back to photons: people sometimes wonder whether it makes
- sense to talk about the "rest mass" of a particle that can never be at
- rest. The answer, again, is that "rest mass" is really a misnomer, and it
- is not necessary for a particle to be at rest for the concept of mass to
- make sense. Technically, it is the invariant length of the particle's
- four-momentum. (You can see this from Eq. (4).) For all photons this is
- zero. On the other hand, the "relativistic mass" of photons is frequency
- dependent. UV photons are more energetic than visible photons, and so are
- more "massive" in this sense, a statement which obscures more than it
- elucidates.
-
- Reference: Lev Okun wrote a nice article on this subject in the
- June 1989 issue of Physics Today, which includes a historical discussion
- of the concept of mass in relativistic physics.
-
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 24.
- updated 16-MAR-1992 by SIC
- Original by John Blanton
- Why Do Stars Twinkle While Planets Do Not?
- -----------------------------------------
-
- Stars, except for the Sun, although they may be millions of miles
- in diameter, are very far away. They appear as point sources even when
- viewed by telescopes. The planets in our solar system, much smaller than
- stars, are closer and can be resolved as disks with a little bit of
- magnification (field binoculars, for example).
-
- Since the Earth's atmosphere is turbulent, all images viewed up
- through it tend to "swim." The result of this is that sometimes a single
- point in object space gets mapped to two or more points in image space, and
- also sometimes a single point in object space does not get mapped into any
- point in image space. When a star's single point in object space fails to
- map to at least one point in image space, the star seems to disappear
- temporarily. This does not mean the star's light is lost for that moment.
- It just means that it didn't get to your eye, it went somewhere else.
-
- Since planets represent several points in object space, it is
- highly likely that one or more points in the planet's object space get
- mapped to a points in image space, and the planet's image never winks out.
- Each individual ray is twinkling away as badly as any star, but when all of
- those individual rays are viewed together, the next effect is averaged out
- to something considerably steadier.
-
- The result is that stars tend to twinkle, and planets do not.
- Other extended objects in space, even very far ones like nebulae, do not
- twinkle if they are sufficiently large that they have non-zero apparent
- diameter when viewed from the Earth.
-
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 25. original by David Brahm
-
- Baryogenesis - Why Are There More Protons Than Antiprotons?
- -----------------------------------------------------------
-
- (I) How do we really *know* that the universe is not matter-antimatter
- symmetric?
-
- (a) The Moon: Neil Armstrong did not annihilate, therefore the moon
- is made of matter.
- (b) The Sun: Solar cosmic rays are matter, not antimatter.
- (c) The other Planets: We have sent probes to almost all. Their survival
- demonstrates that the solar system is made of matter.
- (d) The Milky Way: Cosmic rays sample material from the entire galaxy.
- In cosmic rays, protons outnumber antiprotons 10^4 to 1.
- (e) The Universe at large: This is tougher. If there were antimatter
- galaxies then we should see gamma emissions from annihilation. Its absence
- is strong evidence that at least the nearby clusters of galaxies (e.g., Virgo)
- are matter-dominated. At larger scales there is little proof.
- However, there is a problem, called the "annihilation catastrophe"
- which probably eliminates the possibility of a matter-antimatter symmetric
- universe. Essentially, causality prevents the separation of large chucks
- of antimatter from matter fast enough to prevent their mutual annihilation
- in in the early universe. So the Universe is most likely matter dominated.
-
- (II) How did it get that way?
-
- Annihilation has made the asymmetry much greater today than in the
- early universe. At the high temperature of the first microsecond, there
- were large numbers of thermal quark-antiquark pairs. K&T estimate 30
- million antiquarks for every 30 million and 1 quarks during this epoch.
- That's a tiny asymmetry. Over time most of the antimatter has annihilated
- with matter, leaving the very small initial excess of matter to dominate
- the Universe.
-
- Here are a few possibilities for why we are matter dominated today:
-
- a) The Universe just started that way.
- Not only is this a rather sterile hypothesis, but it doesn't work under
- the popular "inflation" theories, which dilute any initial abundances.
- b) Baryogenesis occurred around the Grand Unified (GUT) scale (very early).
- Long thought to be the only viable candidate, GUT's generically have
- baryon-violating reactions, such as proton decay (not yet observed).
- c) Baryogenesis occurred at the Electroweak Phase Transition (EWPT).
- This is the era when the Higgs first acquired a vacuum expectation value
- (vev), so other particles acquired masses. Pure Standard Model physics.
-
- Sakharov enumerated 3 necessary conditions for baryogenesis:
-
- (1) Baryon number violation. If baryon number is conserved in all
- reactions, then the present baryon asymmetry can only reflect asymmetric
- initial conditions, and we are back to case (a), above.
- (2) C and CP violation. Even in the presence of B-violating
- reactions, without a preference for matter over antimatter the B-violation
- will take place at the same rate in both directions, leaving no excess.
- (3) Thermodynamic Nonequilibrium. Because CPT guarantees equal
- masses for baryons and antibaryons, chemical equilibrium would drive the
- necessary reactions to correct for any developing asymmetry.
-
- It turns out the Standard Model satisfies all 3 conditions:
-
- (1) Though the Standard Model conserves B classically (no terms in
- the Lagrangian violate B), quantum effects allow the universe to tunnel
- between vacua with different values of B. This tunneling is _very_
- suppressed at energies/temperatures below 10 TeV (the "sphaleron mass"),
- _may_ occur at e.g. SSC energies (controversial), and _certainly_ occurs at
- higher temperatures.
-
- (2) C-violation is commonplace. CP-violation (that's "charge
- conjugation" and "parity") has been experimentally observed in kaon
- decays, though strictly speaking the Standard Model probably has
- insufficient CP-violation to give the observed baryon asymmetry.
-
- (3) Thermal nonequilibrium is achieved during first-order phase
- transitions in the cooling early universe, such as the EWPT (at T = 100 GeV
- or so). As bubbles of the "true vacuum" (with a nonzero Higgs vev)
- percolate and grow, baryogenesis can occur at or near the bubble walls.
-
- A major theoretical problem, in fact, is that there may be _too_
- _much_ B-violation in the Standard Model, so that after the EWPT is
- complete (and condition 3 above is no longer satisfied) any previously
- generated baryon asymmetry would be washed out.
-
- References: Kolb and Turner, _The Early Universe_;
- Dine, Huet, Singleton & Susskind, Phys.Lett.B257:351 (1991);
- Dine, Leigh, Huet, Linde & Linde, Phys.Rev.D46:550 (1992).
-
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 26.
-
- TIME TRAVEL - FACT OR FICTION? updated 07-MAR-1994
- ------------------------------ original by Jon J. Thaler
-
- We define time travel to mean departure from a certain place and
- time followed (from the traveller's point of view) by arrival at the same
- place at an earlier (from the sedentary observer's point of view) time.
- Time travel paradoxes arise from the fact that departure occurs after
- arrival according to one observer and before arrival according to another.
- In the terminology of special relativity time travel implies that the
- timelike ordering of events is not invariant. This violates our intuitive
- notions of causality. However, intuition is not an infallible guide, so we
- must be careful. Is time travel really impossible, or is it merely another
- phenomenon where "impossible" means "nature is weirder than we think?" The
- answer is more interesting than you might think.
-
- THE SCIENCE FICTION PARADIGM:
-
- The B-movie image of the intrepid chrononaut climbing into his time
- machine and watching the clock outside spin backwards while those outside
- the time machine watch the him revert to callow youth is, according to
- current theory, impossible. In current theory, the arrow of time flows in
- only one direction at any particular place. If this were not true, then
- one could not impose a 4-dimensional coordinate system on space-time, and
- many nasty consequences would result. Nevertheless, there is a scenario
- which is not ruled out by present knowledge. This usually requires an
- unusual spacetime topology (due to wormholes or strings in general
- relativity) which has not not yet seen, but which may be possible. In
- this scenario the universe is well behaved in every local region; only by
- exploring the global properties does one discover time travel.
-
- CONSERVATION LAWS:
-
- It is sometimes argued that time travel violates conservation laws.
- For example, sending mass back in time increases the amount of energy that
- exists at that time. Doesn't this violate conservation of energy? This
- argument uses the concept of a global conservation law, whereas
- relativistically invariant formulations of the equations of physics only
- imply local conservation. A local conservation law tells us that the
- amount of stuff inside a small volume changes only when stuff flows in or
- out through the surface. A global conservation law is derived from this by
- integrating over all space and assuming that there is no flow in or out at
- infinity. If this integral cannot be performed, then global conservation
- does not follow. So, sending mass back in time might be alright, but it
- implies that something strange is happening. (Why shouldn't we be able to
- do the integral?)
-
- GENERAL RELATIVITY:
-
- One case where global conservation breaks down is in general
- relativity. It is well known that global conservation of energy does not
- make sense in an expanding universe. For example, the universe cools as it
- expands; where does the energy go? See FAQ article #4 - Energy
- Conservation in Cosmology, for details.
-
- It is interesting to note that the possibility of time travel in GR
- has been known at least since 1949 (by Kurt Godel, discussed in [1], page
- 168). The GR spacetime found by Godel has what are now called "closed
- timelike curves" (CTCs). A CTC is a worldline that a particle or a person
- can follow which ends at the same spacetime point (the same position and
- time) as it started. A solution to GR which contains CTCs cannot have a
- spacelike embedding - space must have "holes" (as in donut holes, not holes
- punched in a sheet of paper). A would-be time traveller must go around or
- through the holes in a clever way.
-
- The Godel solution is a curiosity, not useful for constructing a
- time machine. Two recent proposals, one by Morris, et al. [2] and one by
- Gott [3], have the possibility of actually leading to practical devices (if
- you believe this, I have a bridge to sell you). As with Godel, in these
- schemes nothing is locally strange; time travel results from the unusual
- topology of spacetime. The first uses a wormhole (the inner part of a
- black hole, see fig. 1 of [2]) which is held open and manipulated by
- electromagnetic forces. The second uses the conical geometry generated by
- an infinitely long string of mass. If two strings pass by each other, a
- clever person can go into the past by traveling a figure-eight path around
- the strings. In this scenario, if the string has non-zero diameter and
- finite mass density, there is a CTC without any unusual topology.
-
- GRANDFATHER PARADOXES:
-
- With the demonstration that general relativity contains CTCs,
- people began studying the problem of self-consistency. Basically, the
- problem is that of the "grandfather paradox:" What happens if our time
- traveller kills her grandmother before her mother was born? In more
- readily analyzable terms, one can ask what are the implications of the
- quantum mechanical interference of the particle with its future self.
- Boulware [5] shows that there is a problem - unitarity is violated. This is
- related to the question of when one can do the global conservation integral
- discussed above. It is an example of the "Cauchy problem" [1, chapter 7].
-
- OTHER PROBLEMS (and an escape hatch?):
-
- How does one avoid the paradox that a simple solution to GR has
- CTCs which QM does not like? This is not a matter of applying a theory in
- a domain where it is expected to fail. One relevant issue is the
- construction of the time machine. After all, infinite strings aren't
- easily obtained. In fact, it has been shown [4] that Gott's scenario
- implies that the total 4-momentum of spacetime must be spacelike. This
- seems to imply that one cannot build a time machine from any collection of
- non-tachyonic objects, whose 4-momentum must be timelike. There are
- implementation problems with the wormhole method as well.
-
- TACHYONS:
-
- Finally, a diversion on a possibly related topic.
-
- If tachyons exist as physical objects, causality is no longer
- invariant. Different observers will see different causal sequences. This
- effect requires only special relativity (not GR), and follows from the fact
- that for any spacelike trajectory, reference frames can be found in which
- the particle moves backward or forward in time. This is illustrated by the
- pair of spacetime diagrams below. One must be careful about what is
- actually observed; a particle moving backward in time is observed to be a
- forward moving anti-particle, so no observer interprets this as time
- travel.
-
- t
- One reference | Events A and C are at the same
- frame: | place. C occurs first.
- |
- | Event B lies outside the causal
- | B domain of events A and C.
- -----------A----------- x (The intervals are spacelike).
- |
- C In this frame, tachyon signals
- | travel from A-->B and from C-->B.
- | That is, A and C are possible causes
- of event B.
-
- Another t
- reference | Events A and C are not at the same
- frame: | place. C occurs first.
- |
- | Event B lies outside the causal
- -----------A----------- x domain of events A and C. (The
- | intervals are spacelike)
- |
- | C In this frame, signals travel from
- | B-->A and from B-->C. B is the cause
- | B of both of the other two events.
-
- The unusual situation here arises because conventional causality
- assumes no superluminal motion. This tachyon example is presented to
- demonstrate that our intuitive notion of causality may be flawed, so one
- must be careful when appealing to common sense. See FAQ article # 7 -
- Tachyons, for more about these weird hypothetical particles.
-
- CONCLUSION:
-
- The possible existence of time machines remains an open question.
- None of the papers criticizing the two proposals are willing to
- categorically rule out the possibility. Nevertheless, the notion of time
- machines seems to carry with it a serious set of problems.
-
- REFERENCES:
-
- 1: S.W. Hawking, and G.F.R. Ellis, "The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time,"
- Cambridge University Press, 1973.
- 2: M.S. Morris, K.S. Thorne, and U. Yurtsever, PRL, v.61, p.1446 (1989).
- --> How wormholes can act as time machines.
- 3: J.R. Gott, III, PRL, v.66, p.1126 (1991).
- --> How pairs of cosmic strings can act as time machines.
- 4: S. Deser, R. Jackiw, and G. 't Hooft, PRL, v.66, p.267 (1992).
- --> A critique of Gott. You can't construct his machine.
- 5: D.G. Boulware, University of Washington preprint UW/PT-92-04.
- Available on the hep-th@xxx.lanl.gov bulletin board: item number 9207054.
- --> Unitarity problems in QM with closed timelike curves.
- 6: "Nature", May 7, 1992
- --> Contains a very well written review with some nice figures.
-
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 27.
-
- The EPR Paradox and Bell's Inequality Principle updated 31-AUG-1993 by SIC
- ----------------------------------------------- original by John Blanton
-
- In 1935 Albert Einstein and two colleagues, Boris Podolsky and
- Nathan Rosen (EPR) developed a thought experiment to demonstrate what they
- felt was a lack of completeness in quantum mechanics. This so-called "EPR
- paradox" has lead to much subsequent, and still on-going, research. This
- article is an introduction to EPR, Bell's inequality, and the real
- experiments which have attempted to address the interesting issues raised
- by this discussion.
-
- One of the principle features of quantum mechanics is that not all
- the classical physical observables of a system can be simultaneously known,
- either in practice or in principle. Instead, there may be several sets of
- observables which give qualitatively different, but nonetheless complete
- (maximal possible) descriptions of a quantum mechanical system. These sets
- are sets of "good quantum numbers," and are also known as "maximal sets of
- commuting observables." Observables from different sets are "noncommuting
- observables."
-
- A well known example of noncommuting observables are position and
- momentum. You can put a subatomic particle into a state of well-defined
- momentum, but then you cannot know where it is - it is, in fact, everywhere
- at once. It's not just a matter of your inability to measure, but rather,
- an intrinsic property of the particle. Conversely, you can put a particle
- in a definite position, but then it's momentum is completely ill-defined.
- You can also create states of intermediate knowledge of both observables:
- If you confine the particle to some arbitrarily large region of space,
- you can define the momentum more and more precisely. But you can never
- know both, exactly, at the same time.
-
- Position and momentum are continuous observables. But the same
- situation can arise for discrete observables such as spin. The quantum
- mechanical spin of a particle along each of the three space axes are a set
- of mutually noncommuting observables. You can only know the spin along one
- axis at a time. A proton with spin "up" along the x-axis has undefined
- spin along the y and z axes. You cannot simultaneously measure the x and y
- spin projections of a proton. EPR sought to demonstrate that this
- phenomenon could be exploited to construct an experiment which would
- demonstrate a paradox which they believed was inherent in the
- quantum-mechanical description of the world.
-
- They imagined two physical systems that are allowed to interact
- initially so that they subsequently will be defined by a single Schrodinger
- wave equation (SWE). [For simplicity, imagine a simple physical
- realization of this idea - a neutral pion at rest in your lab, which decays
- into a pair of back-to-back photons. The pair of photons is described
- by a single two-particle wave function.] Once separated, the two systems
- [read: photons] are still described by the same SWE, and a measurement of
- one observable of the first system will determine the measurement of the
- corresponding observable of the second system. [Example: The neutral pion
- is a scalar particle - it has zero angular momentum. So the two photons
- must speed off in opposite directions with opposite spin. If photon 1
- is found to have spin up along the x-axis, then photon 2 *must* have spin
- down along the x-axis, since the total angular momentum of the final-state,
- two-photon, system must be the same as the angular momentum of the intial
- state, a single neutral pion. You know the spin of photon 2 even without
- measuring it.] Likewise, the measurement of another observable of the first
- system will determine the measurement of the corresponding observable of the
- second system, even though the systems are no longer physically linked in
- the traditional sense of local coupling.
-
- However, QM prohibits the simultaneous knowledge of more than one
- mutually noncommuting observable of either system. The paradox of EPR is
- the following contradiction: For our coupled systems, we can measure
- observable A of system I [for example, photon 1 has spin up along the
- x-axis; photon 2 must therefore have x-spin down.] and observable B of
- system II [for example, photon 2 has spin down along the y-axis; therefore
- the y-spin of photon 1 must be up.] thereby revealing both observables for
- both systems, contrary to QM.
-
- QM dictates that this should be impossible, creating the
- paradoxical implication that measuring one system should "poison" any
- measurement of the other system, no matter what the distance between
- them. [In one commonly studied interpretation, the mechanism by which
- this proceeds is 'instantaneous collapse of the wavefunction'. But
- the rules of QM do not require this interpretation, and several
- other perfectly valid interpretations exist.] The second system
- would instantaneously be put into a state of well-defined observable A,
- and, consequently, ill-defined observable B, spoiling the measurement.
- Yet, one could imagine the two measurements were so far apart in
- space that special relativity would prohibit any influence of one
- measurement over the other. [After the neutral-pion decay, we can wait until
- the two photons are a light-year apart, and then "simultaneously" measure
- the x-spin of photon 1 and the y-spin of photon 2. QM suggests that if,
- for example, the measurement of the photon 1 x-spin happens first, this
- measurement must instantaneously force photon 2 into a state of ill-defined
- y-spin, even though it is light-years away from photon 1.
-
- How do we reconcile the fact that photon 2 "knows" that the x-spin
- of photon 1 has been measured, even though they are separated by
- light-years of space and far too little time has passed for information
- to have travelled to it according to the rules of Special Relativity?
- There are basically two choices. You can accept the postulates of QM"
- as a fact of life, in spite of its seemingly uncomfortable coexistence
- with special relativity, or you can postulate that QM is not complete,
- that there *was* more information available for the description of the
- two-particle system at the time it was created, carried away by both
- photons, and that you just didn't know it because QM does not properly
- account for it.
-
- So, EPR postulated the existence of hidden variables, some so-far
- unknown properties, of the systems should account for the discrepancy.
- Their claim was that QM theory is incomplete; it does not completely
- describe the physical reality. System II knows all about System I
- long before the scientist measures any of the observables, and thereby
- supposedly consigning the other noncommuting observables to obscurity.
- No instantaneous action-at-a-distance is necessary in this picture,
- which postulates that each System has more parameters than are
- accounted by QM. Niels Bohr, one of the founders of QM, held the opposite
- view and defended a strict interpretation, the Copenhagen Interpretation,
- of QM.
-
- In 1964 John S. Bell proposed a mechanism to test for the existence
- of these hidden parameters, and he developed his inequality principle as
- the basis for such a test.
-
- Use the example of two photons configured in the singlet state,
- consider this: After separation, each photon will have spin values for
- each of the three axes of space, and each spin can have one of two values;
- call them up and down. Call the axes A, B and C and call the spin in the A
- axis A+ if it is up in that axis, otherwise call it A-. Use similar
- definitions for the other two axes.
-
- Now perform the experiment. Measure the spin in one axis of one
- particle and the spin in another axis of the other photon. If EPR were
- correct, each photon will simultaneously have properties for spin in each
- of axes A, B and C.
-
- Look at the statistics. Perform the measurements with a number of
- sets of photons. Use the symbol N(A+, B-) to designate the words "the
- number of photons with A+ and B-." Similarly for N(A+, B+), N(B-, C+),
- etc. Also use the designation N(A+, B-, C+) to mean "the number of photons
- with A+, B- and C+," and so on. It's easy to demonstrate that for a set of
- photons
-
- (1) N(A+, B-) = N(A+, B-, C+) + N(A+, B-, C-)
-
- because all of the (A+, B-, C+) and all of the (A+, B-, C-) photons are
- included in the designation (A+, B-), and nothing else is included in N(A+,
- B-). You can make this claim if these measurements are connected to some
- real properties of the photons.
-
- Let n[A+, B+] be the designation for "the number of measurements of
- pairs of photons in which the first photon measured A+, and the second
- photon measured B+." Use a similar designation for the other possible
- results. This is necessary because this is all it is possible to measure.
- You can't measure both A and B of the same photon. Bell demonstrated that
- in an actual experiment, if (1) is true (indicating real properties), then
- the following must be true:
-
- (2) n[A+, B+] <= n[A+, C+] + n[B+, C-].
-
- Additional inequality relations can be written by just making the
- appropriate permutations of the letters A, B and C and the two signs. This
- is Bell's inequality principle, and it is proved to be true if there are
- real (perhaps hidden) parameters to account for the measurements.
-
- At the time Bell's result first became known, the experimental
- record was reviewed to see if any known results provided evidence against
- locality. None did. Thus an effort began to develop tests of Bell's
- inequality. A series of experiments was conducted by Aspect ending with one
- in which polarizer angles were changed while the photons were `in flight'.
- This was widely regarded at the time as being a reasonably conclusive
- experiment confirming the predictions of QM.
-
- Three years later Franson published a paper showing that the timing
- constraints in this experiment were not adequate to confirm that locality
- was violated. Aspect measured the time delays between detections of photon
- pairs. The critical time delay is that between when a polarizer angle is
- changed and when this affects the statistics of detecting photon pairs.
- Aspect estimated this time based on the speed of a photon and the distance
- between the polarizers and the detectors. Quantum mechanics does not allow
- making assumptions about *where* a particle is between detections. We
- cannot know *when* a particle traverses a polarizer unless we detect the
- particle *at* the polarizer.
-
- Experimental tests of Bell's inequality are ongoing but none has
- yet fully addressed the issue raised by Franson. In addition there is an
- issue of detector efficiency. By postulating new laws of physics one can
- get the expected correlations without any nonlocal effects unless the
- detectors are close to 90% efficient. The importance of these issues is a
- matter of judgement.
-
- The subject is alive theoretically as well. In the 1970's
- Eberhard derived Bell's result without reference to local hidden variable
- theories; it applies to all local theories. Eberhard also showed that the
- nonlocal effects that QM predicts cannot be used for superluminal
- communication. The subject is not yet closed, and may yet provide more
- interesting insights into the subtleties of quantum mechanics.
-
- REFERENCES:
-
- 1. A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, N. Rosen: "Can quantum-mechanical
- description of physical reality be considered complete?"
- Physical Review 41, 777 (15 May 1935). (The original EPR paper)
-
- 2. D. Bohm: Quantum Theory, Dover, New York (1957). (Bohm
- discusses some of his ideas concerning hidden variables.)
-
- 3. N. Herbert: Quantum Reality, Doubleday. (A very good
- popular treatment of EPR and related issues)
-
- 4. M. Gardner: Science - Good, Bad and Bogus, Prometheus Books.
- (Martin Gardner gives a skeptics view of the fringe science
- associated with EPR.)
-
- 5. J. Gribbin: In Search of Schrodinger's Cat, Bantam Books.
- (A popular treatment of EPR and the paradox of "Schrodinger's
- cat" that results from the Copenhagen interpretation)
-
- 6. N. Bohr: "Can quantum-mechanical description of physical
- reality be considered complete?" Physical Review 48, 696 (15 Oct
- 1935). (Niels Bohr's response to EPR)
-
- 7. J. Bell: "On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox" Physics 1
- #3, 195 (1964).
-
- 8. J. Bell: "On the problem of hidden variables in quantum
- mechanics" Reviews of Modern Physics 38 #3, 447 (July 1966).
-
- 9. D. Bohm, J. Bub: "A proposed solution of the measurement
- problem in quantum mechanics by a hidden variable theory"
- Reviews of Modern Physics 38 #3, 453 (July 1966).
-
- 10. B. DeWitt: "Quantum mechanics and reality" Physics Today p.
- 30 (Sept 1970).
-
- 11. J. Clauser, A. Shimony: "Bell's theorem: experimental
- tests and implications" Rep. Prog. Phys. 41, 1881 (1978).
-
- 12. A. Aspect, Dalibard, Roger: "Experimental test of Bell's
- inequalities using time- varying analyzers" Physical Review
- Letters 49 #25, 1804 (20 Dec 1982).
-
- 13. A. Aspect, P. Grangier, G. Roger: "Experimental realization
- of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm gedankenexperiment; a new
- violation of Bell's inequalities" Physical Review Letters 49
- #2, 91 (12 July 1982).
-
- 14. A. Robinson: "Loophole closed in quantum mechanics test"
- Science 219, 40 (7 Jan 1983).
-
- 15. B. d'Espagnat: "The quantum theory and reality" Scientific
- American 241 #5 (November 1979).
-
- 16. "Bell's Theorem and Delayed Determinism", Franson, Physical Review D,
- pgs. 2529-2532, Vol. 31, No. 10, May 1985.
-
- 17. "Bell's Theorem without Hidden Variables", P. H. Eberhard, Il Nuovo
- Cimento, 38 B 1, pgs. 75-80, (1977).
-
- 18. "Bell's Theorem and the Different Concepts of Locality", P. H.
- Eberhard, Il Nuovo Cimento 46 B, pgs. 392-419, (1978).
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 28.
-
- The Nobel Prize for Physics (1901-1993) updated 15-OCT-1993 by SIC
- --------------------------------------- original by Scott I. Chase
-
- The following is a complete listing of Nobel Prize awards, from the first
- award in 1901. Prizes were not awarded in every year. The description
- following the names is an abbreviation of the official citation.
-
- 1901 Wilhelm Konrad Rontgen X-rays
- 1902 Hendrik Antoon Lorentz Magnetism in radiation phenomena
- Pieter Zeeman
- 1903 Antoine Henri Bequerel Spontaneous radioactivity
- Pierre Curie
- Marie Sklowdowska-Curie
- 1904 Lord Rayleigh Density of gases and
- (a.k.a. John William Strutt) discovery of argon
- 1905 Pilipp Eduard Anton von Lenard Cathode rays
- 1906 Joseph John Thomson Conduction of electricity by gases
- 1907 Albert Abraham Michelson Precision meteorological investigations
- 1908 Gabriel Lippman Reproducing colors photographically
- based on the phenomenon of interference
- 1909 Guglielmo Marconi Wireless telegraphy
- Carl Ferdinand Braun
- 1910 Johannes Diderik van der Waals Equation of state of fluids
- 1911 Wilhelm Wien Laws of radiation of heat
- 1912 Nils Gustaf Dalen Automatic gas flow regulators
- 1913 Heike Kamerlingh Onnes Matter at low temperature
- 1914 Max von Laue Crystal diffraction of X-rays
- 1915 William Henry Bragg X-ray analysis of crystal structure
- William Lawrence Bragg
- 1917 Charles Glover Barkla Characteristic X-ray spectra of elements
- 1918 Max Planck Energy quanta
- 1919 Johannes Stark Splitting of spectral lines in E fields
- 1920 Charles-Edouard Guillaume Anomalies in nickel steel alloys
- 1921 Albert Einstein Photoelectric Effect
- 1922 Niels Bohr Structure of atoms
- 1923 Robert Andrew Millikan Elementary charge of electricity
- 1924 Karl Manne Georg Siegbahn X-ray spectroscopy
- 1925 James Franck Impact of an electron upon an atom
- Gustav Hertz
- 1926 Jean Baptiste Perrin Sedimentation equilibrium
- 1927 Arthur Holly Compton Compton effect
- Charles Thomson Rees Wilson Invention of the Cloud chamber
- 1928 Owen Willans Richardson Thermionic phenomena, Richardson's Law
- 1929 Prince Louis-Victor de Broglie Wave nature of electrons
- 1930 Sir Chandrasekhara Venkata Raman Scattering of light, Raman effect
- 1932 Werner Heisenberg Quantum Mechanics
- 1933 Erwin Schrodinger Atomic theory
- Paul Adrien Maurice Dirac
- 1935 James Chadwick The neutron
- 1936 Victor Franz Hess Cosmic rays
- Carl D. Anderson The positron
- 1937 Clinton Joseph Davisson Crystal diffraction of electrons
- George Paget Thomson
- 1938 Enrico Fermi New radioactive elements
- 1939 Ernest Orlando Lawrence Invention of the Cyclotron
- 1943 Otto Stern Proton magnetic moment
- 1944 Isador Isaac Rabi Magnetic resonance in atomic nuclei
- 1945 Wolfgang Pauli The Exclusion principle
- 1946 Percy Williams Bridgman Production of extremely high pressures
- 1947 Sir Edward Victor Appleton Physics of the upper atmosphere
- 1948 Patrick Maynard Stuart Blackett Cosmic ray showers in cloud chambers
- 1949 Hideki Yukawa Prediction of Mesons
- 1950 Cecil Frank Powell Photographic emulsion for meson studies
- 1951 Sir John Douglas Cockroft Artificial acceleration of atomic
- Ernest Thomas Sinton Walton particles and transmutation of nuclei
- 1952 Felix Bloch Nuclear magnetic precision methods
- Edward Mills Purcell
- 1953 Frits Zernike Phase-contrast microscope
- 1954 Max Born Fundamental research in QM
- Walther Bothe Coincidence counters
- 1955 Willis Eugene Lamb Hydrogen fine structure
- Polykarp Kusch Electron magnetic moment
- 1956 William Shockley Transistors
- John Bardeen
- Walter Houser Brattain
- 1957 Chen Ning Yang Parity violation
- Tsung Dao Lee
- 1958 Pavel Aleksejevic Cerenkov Interpretation of the Cerenkov effect
- Il'ja Mickajlovic Frank
- Igor' Evgen'evic Tamm
- 1959 Emilio Gino Segre The Antiproton
- Owen Chamberlain
- 1960 Donald Arthur Glaser The Bubble Chamber
- 1961 Robert Hofstadter Electron scattering on nucleons
- Rudolf Ludwig Mossbauer Resonant absorption of photons
- 1962 Lev Davidovic Landau Theory of liquid helium
- 1963 Eugene P. Wigner Fundamental symmetry principles
- Maria Goeppert Mayer Nuclear shell structure
- J. Hans D. Jensen
- 1964 Charles H. Townes Maser-Laser principle
- Nikolai G. Basov
- Alexander M. Prochorov
- 1965 Sin-Itiro Tomonaga Quantum electrodynamics
- Julian Schwinger
- Richard P. Feynman
- 1966 Alfred Kastler Study of Hertzian resonance in atoms
- 1967 Hans Albrecht Bethe Energy production in stars
- 1968 Luis W. Alvarez Discovery of many particle resonances
- 1969 Murray Gell-Mann Quark model for particle classification
- 1970 Hannes Alfven Magneto-hydrodynamics in plasma physics
- Louis Neel Antiferromagnetism and ferromagnetism
- 1971 Dennis Gabor Principles of holography
- 1972 John Bardeen Superconductivity
- Leon N. Cooper
- J. Robert Schrieffer
- 1973 Leo Esaki Tunneling in superconductors
- Ivar Giaever
- Brian D. Josephson Super-current through tunnel barriers
- 1974 Antony Hewish Discovery of pulsars
- Sir Martin Ryle Pioneering radioastronomy work
- 1975 Aage Bohr Structure of the atomic nucleus
- Ben Mottelson
- James Rainwater
- 1976 Burton Richter Discovery of the J/Psi particle
- Samual Chao Chung Ting
- 1977 Philip Warren Anderson Electronic structure of magnetic and
- Nevill Francis Mott disordered solids
- John Hasbrouck Van Vleck
- 1978 Pyotr Kapitsa Liquifaction of helium
- Arno A. Penzias Cosmic Microwave Background Radiation
- Robert W. Wilson
- 1979 Sheldon Glashow Electroweak Theory, especially
- Steven Weinberg weak neutral currents
- Abdus Salam
- 1980 James Cronin Discovery of CP violation in the
- Val Fitch asymmetric decay of neutral K-mesons
- 1981 Kai M. Seigbahn High resolution electron spectroscopy
- Nicolaas Bleombergen Laser spectroscopy
- Arthur L. Schawlow
- 1982 Kenneth G. Wilson Critical phenomena in phase transitions
- 1983 Subrahmanyan Chandrasekhar Evolution of stars
- William A. Fowler
- 1984 Carlo Rubbia Discovery of W,Z
- Simon van der Meer Stochastic cooling for colliders
- 1985 Klaus von Klitzing Discovery of quantum Hall effect
- 1986 Gerd Binning Scanning Tunneling Microscopy
- Heinrich Rohrer
- Ernst August Friedrich Ruska Electron microscopy
- 1987 Georg Bednorz High-temperature superconductivity
- Alex K. Muller
- 1988 Leon Max Lederman Discovery of the muon neutrino leading
- Melvin Schwartz to classification of particles in
- Jack Steinberger families
- 1989 Hans Georg Dehmelt Penning Trap for charged particles
- Wolfgang Paul Paul Trap for charged particles
- Norman F. Ramsey Control of atomic transitions by the
- separated oscillatory fields method
- 1990 Jerome Isaac Friedman Deep inelastic scattering experiments
- Henry Way Kendall leading to the discovery of quarks
- Richard Edward Taylor
- 1991 Pierre-Gilles de Gennes Order-disorder transitions in liquid
- crystals and polymers
- 1992 Georges Charpak Multiwire Proportional Chamber
- 1993 Russell A. Hulse Discovery of the first binary pulsar
- Joseph H. Taylor and subsequent tests of GR
-
- ********************************************************************************
- Item 29.
-
- Open Questions updated 01-JUN-1993 by SIC
- -------------- original by John Baez
-
- While for the most part a FAQ covers the answers to frequently
- asked questions whose answers are known, in physics there are also plenty
- of simple and interesting questions whose answers are not known. Before you
- set about answering these questions on your own, it's worth noting that
- while nobody knows what the answers are, there has been at least a little,
- and sometimes a great deal, of work already done on these subjects. People
- have said a lot of very intelligent things about many of these questions.
- So do plenty of research and ask around before you try to cook up a theory
- that'll answer one of these and win you the Nobel prize! You can expect to
- really know physics inside and out before you make any progress on these.
-
- The following partial list of "open" questions is divided into two
- groups, Cosmology and Astrophysics, and Particle and Quantum Physics.
- However, given the implications of particle physics on cosmology, the
- division is somewhat artificial, and, consequently, the categorization is
- somewhat arbitrary.
-
- (There are many other interesting and fundamental questions in
- fields such as condensed matter physics, nonlinear dynamics, etc., which
- are not part of the set of related questions in cosmology and quantum
- physics which are discussed below. Their omission is not a judgement
- about importance, but merely a decision about the scope of this article.)
-
- Cosmology and Astrophysics
- --------------------------
-
- 1. What happened at, or before the Big Bang? Was there really an initial
- singularity? Of course, this question might not make sense, but it might.
- Does the history of universe go back in time forever, or only a finite
- amount?
-
- 2. Will the future of the universe go on forever or not? Will there be a
- "big crunch" in the future? Is the Universe infinite in spatial extent?
-
- 3. Why is there an arrow of time; that is, why is the future so much
- different from the past?
-
- 4. Is spacetime really four-dimensional? If so, why - or is that just a
- silly question? Or is spacetime not really a manifold at all if examined
- on a short enough distance scale?
-
- 5. Do black holes really exist? (It sure seems like it.) Do they really
- radiate energy and evaporate the way Hawking predicts? If so, what happens
- when, after a finite amount of time, they radiate completely away? What's
- left? Do black holes really violate all conservation laws except
- conservation of energy, momentum, angular momentum and electric charge?
- What happens to the information contained in an object that falls into a
- black hole? Is it lost when the black hole evaporates? Does this require
- a modification of quantum mechanics?
-
- 6. Is the Cosmic Censorship Hypothesis true? Roughly, for generic
- collapsing isolated gravitational systems are the singularities that might
- develop guaranteed to be hidden beyond a smooth event horizon? If Cosmic
- Censorship fails, what are these naked singularities like? That is, what
- weird physical consequences would they have?
-
- 7. Why are the galaxies distributed in clumps and filaments? Is most of
- the matter in the universe baryonic? Is this a matter to be resolved by
- new physics?
-
- 8. What is the nature of the missing "Dark Matter"? Is it baryonic,
- neutrinos, or something more exotic?
-
- Particle and Quantum Physics
- ----------------------------
-
- 1. Why are the laws of physics not symmetrical between left and right,
- future and past, and between matter and antimatter? I.e., what is the
- mechanism of CP violation, and what is the origin of parity violation in
- Weak interactions? Are there right-handed Weak currents too weak to have
- been detected so far? If so, what broke the symmetry? Is CP violation
- explicable entirely within the Standard Model, or is some new force or
- mechanism required?
-
- 2. Why are the strengths of the fundamental forces (electromagnetism, weak
- and strong forces, and gravity) what they are? For example, why is the
- fine structure constant, which measures the strength of electromagnetism,
- about 1/137.036? Where did this dimensionless constant of nature come from?
- Do the forces really become Grand Unified at sufficiently high energy?
-
- 3. Why are there 3 generations of leptons and quarks? Why are there mass
- ratios what they are? For example, the muon is a particle almost exactly
- like the electron except about 207 times heavier. Why does it exist and
- why precisely that much heavier? Do the quarks or leptons have any
- substructure?
-
- 4. Is there a consistent and acceptable relativistic quantum field theory
- describing interacting (not free) fields in four spacetime dimensions? For
- example, is the Standard Model mathematically consistent? How about
- Quantum Electrodynamics?
-
- 5. Is QCD a true description of quark dynamics? Is it possible to
- calculate masses of hadrons (such as the proton, neutron, pion, etc.)
- correctly from the Standard Model? Does QCD predict a quark/gluon
- deconfinement phase transition at high temperature? What is the nature of
- the transition? Does this really happen in Nature?
-
- 6. Why is there more matter than antimatter, at least around here? Is
- there really more matter than antimatter throughout the universe?
-
- 7. What is meant by a "measurement" in quantum mechanics? Does
- "wavefunction collapse" actually happen as a physical process? If so, how,
- and under what conditions? If not, what happens instead?
-
- 8. What are the gravitational effects, if any, of the immense (possibly
- infinite) vacuum energy density seemingly predicted by quantum field
- theory? Is it really that huge? If so, why doesn't it act like an
- enormous cosmological constant?
-
- 9. Why doesn't the flux of solar neutrinos agree with predictions? Is the
- disagreement really significant? If so, is the discrepancy in models of
- the sun, theories of nuclear physics, or theories of neutrinos? Are
- neutrinos really massless?
-
- The Big Question (TM)
- ---------------------
-
- This last question sits on the fence between the two categories above:
-
- How do you merge Quantum Mechanics and General Relativity to create a
- quantum theory of gravity? Is Einstein's theory of gravity (classical GR)
- also correct in the microscopic limit, or are there modifications
- possible/required which coincide in the observed limit(s)? Is gravity
- really curvature, or what else -- and why does it then look like curvature?
- An answer to this question will necessarily rely upon, and at the same time
- likely be a large part of, the answers to many of the other questions above.
-
- ********************************************************************************
- END OF FAQ
-
-
-